000 01995cam a2200277zu 4500
001 88923808
003 FRCYB88923808
005 20250107180711.0
006 m o d
007 cr un
008 250107s2021 fr | o|||||0|0|||eng d
020 _a9781773852539
035 _aFRCYB88923808
040 _aFR-PaCSA
_ben
_c
_erda
100 1 _aNorton, John D.
245 0 1 _aThe Material Theory of Induction
_c['Norton, John D.']
264 1 _bUniversity of Calgary Press
_c2021
300 _a p.
336 _btxt
_2rdacontent
337 _bc
_2rdamdedia
338 _bc
_2rdacarrier
650 0 _a
700 0 _aNorton, John D.
856 4 0 _2Cyberlibris
_uhttps://international.scholarvox.com/netsen/book/88923808
_qtext/html
_a
520 _aThe fundamental burden of a theory of inductive inference is to determine which are the good inductive inferences or relations of inductive support and why it is that they are so. The traditional approach is modeled on that taken in accounts of deductive inference. It seeks universally applicable schemas or rules or a single formal device, such as the probability calculus. After millennia of halting efforts, none of these approaches has been unequivocally successful and debates between approaches persist. The Material Theory of Induction identifies the source of these enduring problems in the assumption taken at the outset: that inductive inference can be accommodated by a single formal account with universal applicability. Instead, it argues that that there is no single, universally applicable formal account. Rather, each domain has an inductive logic native to it.The content of that logic and where it can be applied are determined by the facts prevailing in that domain. Paying close attention to how inductive inference is conducted in science and copiously illustrated with real-world examples, The Material Theory of Induction will initiate a new tradition in the analysis of inductive inference.
999 _c52652
_d52651